Internal
Injuries
Some Further Concerns with Intercultural
and Transhistorical
Critique
Colin Wysman
In the Fall 2008 issue of Lyceum,
Jordan Bartol illuminates
some problems with Axel Honneth’s theory of recognition, ultimately
concluding
that it is insufficient for cross-cultural critique. In this paper, I
first
examine the differences between internal and external critique as
described by
Antti Kauppinen, and where both he and Honneth think recognition theory
fits. I
then examine Honneth’s conceptions of self-realization and autonomy and
argue
that despite his attempts as establishing them as a universally held
normative
core for social critique, they are both individually and cultural
relativistic.
Furthermore, in an important departure from Bartol’s argument, I
suggest that
it is not the question of progressive priority that we need to ask of
Honneth’s
notion of historical moral progress. Rather, I contend that we must ask
whether
or not historical moral progress can be used for internal critique at
all,
since, as I argue, it points to external principles. Finally, I
conclude that
Honneth has insufficiently justified his theory of recognition as
universalist
internal critique and that at best, he advocates a mixed stance,
composed of
both internal and external methods of critique.
Forms of Social Critique
Axel Honneth’s recognition theory is
an attempt at
establishing a normative ground for internalist social critique.
Stronger than
its externalist counterpart, this type of critique avoids the charge of
relativism
that can be brought against social criticism that appeals to external
values.
Although the universal norms that external critique appeals to are
independent
of actual human thought and action, it is precisely for this reason
that it is
problematic. As Kauppinen (2002) suggests, value pluralism forces
universalist
principles to be explained in extremely general terms so as to remain
culturally neutral and thus, they become increasingly difficult to turn
to when
making value judgments (pp. 481). As a result, external critique faces
the
problem of either being too broad and abstract for any practical use,
or being
so specific that the user is forced to appeal to principles that are
culturally
relative, thus succumbing to ethnocentrism.
It
is for this reason that internal
critique is such an attractive tool for engaging in moral criticism; it
is able
to pass moral judgments by referring to inherent contradictions within
a
system. Simple internal critique is the most straightforward: by
drawing
attention to the contradiction between explicitly stated parts of a
system, one
is able to judge the system or institution as being morally corrupt or
hypocritical. Kauppinen engages in this type of critique using
organizations
such as the World Bank and IMF as examples. Their explicit purpose, he
writes,
“is to help bring wealth and well-being to developing nations, while
their
actual practices all too often lead to the opposite results” (2002, pp.
484).
Thus, by showing how the explicitly stated goals of a system are
inconsistent
with its actions, one can engage in a simple internal critique of it.
More complicated is a second,
reconstructive form of
internal critique, which requires one to evaluate a system based on
principles
which are not explicitly demonstrated. One can infer these principles
and
attitudes, writes Kauppinen, from the ways in which they are manifest,
which
might include unarticulated emotions and informal sanctions or perhaps
partial
articulations of religious customs and laws (2002, pp. 484). It is a
strong
version of this reconstructive internal critique that he attributes to
Honneth’s philosophy of recognition. Indeed, by
recognizing a subject as
someone deserving of autonomy, rights or social esteem, you are
applying an
implicit normative evaluative framework to them. If this implicit
framework is
violated, as might be the case if certain lifestyles or customs are
looked down
upon (or, using Honneth’s language, denied esteem), then an attempt at
internal
critique, and a struggle for recognition are justifiable.
But
what can be said about the
implicit normative standards of recognition? If Honneth’s theory of
recognition
is to serve as the measure for moral judgments, it must appeal to
principles
that are universally held. What he is attempting to achieve is what
Kauppinen
characterizes as strong reconstructive critique,
which requires that the
implicit norms of mutual recognition in humans ought to tacitly refer
to
universal standards of value (2002, pp. 485). Much like the
difficulties encountered
in universalist external critique, strong internal reconstructivism
must refer
to principles that are broad enough to account for moral pluralism. In Grounding
Recognition, Honneth attempts to answer the challenge put
forth by
Kauppinen. That is, to “[demonstrate] that the norms of recognition
that are
reconstructed in each case are not of a merely contingent character but
have,
rather, necessarily universalistic content”
(Honneth, 2002, pp. 515).
Honneth’s key to this challenge lies in personal autonomy and
self-realization.
The Normative Core of Recognition
A brief examination of Honneth’s
discussion of autonomy is
necessary at this point. In Redistribution as Recognition (2003),
Honneth rejects Nancy Fraser’s two-dimensional theory of recognition
that holds
parity of participation as its core. Her attempt at articulating a
normative
core for recognition holds that recognition claims are justified if
they allow
for increased participation in public life for an individual or group,
without
impinging on anyone else’s ability to do the same (Fraser, 2003, pp.
31).
Honneth rightly criticizes this position as being culturally
relativistic.
Indeed, participation in public life is a virtue that has come to be
held in
high regard within liberal democracies in the West. It is uncertain
whether
parity of participation is valued as highly (or at all, for that
matter) in
other areas of the world. By adopting participatory parity as the
normative
core to her theory of recognition, Fraser is undertaking an
ethnocentric
external critique, though she believes it to be universalist.
Honneth,
in turn, holds that
autonomy and self-realization ought to be held as the normative core of
recognition. He believes that this overcomes the difficulties that
Fraser’s
parity of participation encounters because self-realization draws its
normativity from within the realm of recognition, thus being
internalist. He
writes,
What subjects can regard as dimensions of
their personality for
which they can legitimately expect social recognition at any given time
depends
on the normative mode of their inclusion into society [….] Thus, the
corresponding social morality can also be understood as a normative
articulation of the principles that govern the way subjects recognize
each
other in a given society. (Honneth, 2003, pp. 181)
Thus, rather than refer to an
external principle such as
parity of participation, Honneth holds self-realization as an internal
normative principle, necessarily bound to recognition. The way in which
we form
our personal identity is derived from the relations of recognition that
we
experience. Accordingly, a social morality argues Honneth, is merely an
articulation of the internal normative principles that we hold and
employ when
engaging in recognition relations.
I
find this classification of
self-realization as internal to be problematic however. By positing
self-realization and autonomy as part of the recognition process,
Honneth is
entering into a form of question begging, where both recognition and
self-realization are contingent upon one another. It appears as if he
may be
advocating a stance that self realization is formed through
recognition, while
simultaneously claiming that a social morality is an articulation of
the mutual
recognition of two parties’ identities. If self-realization and
autonomy are
the goals of a struggle for recognition, then one might ask how it is
that an
individual can articulate their need for recognition if an autonomous
image of
the self – only achievable through recognition relations – is required
to do
so. If this is not the case, that recognition and self-realization are
dependent upon one another, then Honneth has indeed escaped this
criticism.
However, it will require him to provide another explanation as to how
autonomy
and self-realization in recognition are capable of internal critique.
In other
words, if the end of self-realization is not accepted as normatively
neutral on
the grounds of its relation to the process of recognition, then he must
show
that it is universally normative in another way.
In
Grounding Recognition
(2002), Honneth articulates his position with this criticism in mind.
His new
stance considers a point made by Kauppinen, challenging the primacy of
the
norms of recognition. This challenge, writes Kauppinen, is “that the
norms of
recognition are derivative from more fundamental
moral norms of
self-realization, and these fundamental norms are relativistic, being
specific
to Western liberal societies that prize individual self-realization
over other
values” (2002, pp. 493). This challenge is similar to the one that
Honneth has
leveled against Fraser’s notion of parity of participation. Just as
Honneth had
accused participation in public life as being a culturally relativistic
virtue,
valued mainly by those in the liberal West, so too can it be argued
that
self-realization is relative, valued mainly by Western liberal
societies, but
not necessarily elsewhere.
Honneth’s
clarification of his
position takes two forms. First, in addressing the claim that the norms
of recognition
are derivative from the norms of self-realization, he rejects the
charge of
instrumentalism that Kauppinen levels against him. He writes, “It would
be a
mistake to follow Kauppinen in speaking of ‘recognition’ as merely
secondary to
a primary goal of ‘self-realization’; on the contrary, the point is
that
individuals’ autonomy can reach its fullest development
only via the
relevant recognitional responses” (2002, PP. 516). In other words,
Honneth is
claiming that self-realization is not the primary goal of recognition
in an
externalist sense. Rather, it is dependent on recognition, as
individuals can
only achieve full autonomy and self-realization through mutual
recognition.
This
claim is troublesome however,
as I find is unreasonable to place the weight of self-realization
entirely on
recognition relations. One could imagine an individual who lives a life
of
solitude as being able to speak of himself as autonomous. Further, it
is unfair
to speak of such an individual as lacking altogether, or having a
deficiently
formed notion of self. Indeed, self-realization and autonomy can be
developed
through relations of recognition; however, recognition ought not to be
considered a necessary condition for them, as Honneth believes. His
talk about
‘full development’ of autonomy through recognition is vague, as he
fails to
clarify both what it means for one to be fully autonomous, and how
recognition
relations hold a monopoly on such development. Thus, his response to
Kauppinen’s charge that relations of recognition are subservient to the
normatively distinct and relativistic goal of self-realization is
insufficient.
In
a second attempt to address the
charge that his conception of autonomy is relativistic, Honneth
describes it as
a more general principle, which he believes can be applied universally.
He
writes that a concept of autonomy or self-realization “should rather
let
differences come to the fore regarding the various cultural ways of
realizing,
within history, the telos of a relation-to-self
that is free from
domination or compulsion” (2002, pp. 517). In defining autonomy and
self-recognition in these terms, he is taking a step back from his
previous
position which had been centered on the Western liberal conception of
“the good
life”. Indeed, by taking a more general approach to autonomy, Honneth
has
adopted a less relativistic stance. However, he has not been able to
fully
eliminate relativism from his position. His argument is that autonomy
and
self-realization are universal, insofar as they are to be considered as
a sort
of liberty for one to establish a relation-to-self free from
domination. This
notion retains, however, a relativistic aspect.
Consider
the military as example.
In such an institution, regulated by principles of strict discipline
and obedience,
autonomy and self-realization are not highly valued. If one were to
pursue full
autonomy within the military organization, as opposed to submitting and
obeying
orders from above, the entire chain of command would be undermined. If
we
imagine one who willfully enters the military - not through coercion or
a draft
– we could see that such an individual comes to form a conception of
the self
as a direct result of domination. It is possible in
this sense to speak
of a soldier who, in being recognized as a soldier, loses autonomy. In
this
case, identity is formed through relations that, under different
circumstances,
might intuitively be called misrecognition. Although one may argue that
an
exercise of autonomy was involved in the initial decision to enlist in
the
military, it cannot be doubted that identity formation and
self-realization are
brought about as a direct result of the domination and obedience
required of
soldiers. Thus, Honneth’s claim that the norms of autonomy and
self-realization
are universalist is dubious; it is clear that self-realization and
autonomy,
although less relativistic than parity of participation, are principles
that
are more highly valued across cultural and demographic groups.
Historical Moral Progress as an
External Evaluative Principle
Up to this point, it has been argued
that the normative core
of Honneth’s philosophy of recognition – autonomy and self-realization
– fails
to capture the universality required in order to undertake strong
internal
reconstructive critique. Indeed, his inability to provide universal
norms has
reduced his theory to a weak reconstructive
internal critique, described
by Kauppinen as relying on “norms that simply happen to structure the
practices
of a particular society” (2002, pp. 485). I shall now proceed to argue
that
Honneth’s philosophy of recognition is not, in fact, a form of internal
critique; rather, it points to external principles when making moral
judgments.
A
crucial aspect of Honneth’s
stance, which has yet to be discussed at this point, is the notion of
moral
progress. In another attempt to show the universality of the norms of
recognition (those of self-realization and autonomy), Honneth argues
that
historical progress holds the key to solving the problem of relativism.
A
distinct feature of the norms of recognition, he writes, is that they
contain a
“normative surplus”.
He explains this concept in Grounding Recognition
where he writes, “even
when there is no apparent gap between the de facto
practices and
implicit norms, the ideals associated with the distinct forms of
recognition
always call for greater degrees of morally appropriate behavior, than
is ever
practiced in that particular reality” (2002, pp. 517). In other words,
no
matter how closely - or even ideally – a society conforms to its
implicit
norms, it always ought to be presupposed that a higher moral reality is
achievable. In this sense, Honneth believes to have overcome the
obstacle of
historical relativism; the norms of recognition are not static, but
rather,
they evolve with history.
This
way of viewing moral progress
as an indicator of normative universality poses some concern however.
Arguably,
the classification of Honneth’s philosophy of recognition as internal
critique
is drawn into question. One is compelled to ask how a principle such as
a
future society functions as an internal norm of a system. By using a
non-existent and hypothetical future reality as the yardstick for
normative
judgment of the current state of affairs, Honneth would appear to be
appealing
to external values.
It
may be argued in Honneth’s
defense though, that although the notion of a normatively superior
future
existence is indeed not an internal feature of a society, it holds
internal
manifestation through the potential inherent within humans or through a
negation of the status quo. Honneth writes, “as a result of the
corresponding
recognitional responses of legal respect, of love, and of esteem,
subjects come
to be able to identify with the three evaluative qualities to which
they always
already potentially have access, independently of
all historical
transformations” (2002, pp. 512). It is indeed possible to say, as
Honneth
implies, that the notion of historical progress is the articulation of
an
internal drive to actualize potentialities. This appears to be a more
accurate
characterization of the ‘surplus of value’ idea; the value horizons of
the
norms of recognition contain within them a notion of value that
transcends the
status quo and posits a qualitatively superior society. He writes that
the
norms of recognition “continually demand, from within themselves, the
further
perfection of our moral action, such that the historical process is
characterized by a permanent pressure to learn” (2002, pp. 517). This
notion
seems somewhat troubling, as it appears as if Honneth is attributing
the desire
for moral perfection and rationality as being inherent in all persons.
This
aside, there is a more important issue to be discussed.
Honneth
claims to be able to avoid
the criticism that historical moral progress is an external principle
by
conceiving of it as a potentiality inherent in individuals. Left at
that,
however, the ability to make moral judgments regarding the current
state of
affairs becomes difficult. Indeed, for Honneth’s norms of recognition
to be
universal and thus allowing him to pursue a strong internal critique,
they
ought to be found in something more concrete than a hypothetical
utopia. It is
for this reason that he turns to the past when passing judgment on the
norms of
recognition. He writes, “in order to show that the currently dominant
norms of
recognition are not just relatively but rather universally valid,
it must be
possible to assert their normative superiority over all previous
recognition
regimes” (2002, pp. 517).
The
necessity for one to use the
past when evaluating the norms of recognition is troublesome. While
Honneth has
been able to argue that recognition holds within it a surplus of value
that
allows individuals to use the implicit norms to posit a better society,
he is
unable to take this approach here. A past ‘recognition regime’ has no
manifestation in the current social state, as neither potentiality nor
actuality. Likewise, determinate negation of the present can speculate
on a
hypothetical future society, however it does not identify the past
norms
recognition or state of affairs.
It
is on this point, I believe,
that Bartol and I differ somewhat. Though I acknowledge that a past
recognition
regime might indeed be manifest in a present society as an evolutionary
prior
value system out of which the current society has grown, the values
themselves
are not necessarily an internal feature of the present society.
Bartol’s
example of the historical expansion of the concepts of personhood and
legal
recognition to include African Americans and Aboriginals illuminates my
point.
If we consider our present day society, S2 to have a value system
evolved from
an earlier stage of society, S1, then even though we can argue that
indeed,
S1’s value system has developed into that of S2, the values
themselves,
mainly, the historically prior conceptions of personhood and legal
recognition
are nowhere to be found among S2’s current value set. Thus, in order
for one to
argue that a present society is morally superior due to its expansion
of legal
recognition and personhood to African Americans and Aboriginals, we
must
necessarily appeal to the value system of the past, whose articulation
lies
outside of the current system.
The
question we ought to ask then,
is exactly what does a society’s value system imply about the past? It
is easy
to say, as Bartol does, that the norms of the present can be considered
to be
an evolved form of the norms of the past, but the concern that I have
is that
the norms of the present provide no descriptive explanation as to their
past
nature. To illustrate this concept with a simple example following
Bartol’s
theme, one can say of society’s present value system that “Our present
society
grants legal recognition to all.” Implicit in this statement is not
“Our past
society granted legal recognition to white people.” In order to access
this
description of a past value system, one must turn to the value system
of the
past, which lies entirely outside of the current system, regardless of
how
clearly its evolutionary progress can be observed. Thus, in evaluating
the
present against the past, one is essentially appealing to a principle
that
exists as entirely external to the social system they seek to evaluate.
Though
I agree with Bartol insofar as I believe Recognition Theory to be an
inadequate
form of transhistorical critique, we differ in our methods of arriving
at this
conclusion. Whereas Bartol has convincingly shown the problems of
historical
moral progress in transcultural critique, I hold that the
very concept
of historical moral progress is inherently flawed due to its dependence
on
external principles and thus, is unable to stand alone as a method of
internal
critique.
Concluding Thoughts
While both Honneth and Kauppinen
characterize Honneth’s
philosophy of recognition as being an instance of strong reconstructive
internal critique, I believe this categorization to be inaccurate.
Autonomy and
self-realization, which serve as the normative core of Honneth’s
Recognition
Theory, are not the universal principles that he believes them to be.
His claim
that recognition is a necessary precondition for the development of
full
autonomy and self-realization is drawn into question when one considers
the
life of a hermit. Although he is not part of a legal system under which
he can claim
to have rights, surely it could be said that he is autonomous.
Moreover, it is
unreasonable to make the claim that he is unable to have a fully formed
conception of himself, or that he is unable to undertake full
self-realization.
Additionally, when one considers the military institution as an example
of a
social construct that places limited value on autonomy and
self-realization,
these principles appear to be at least somewhat relativistic. Whereas
Honneth
describes self-relation as being the development of a relation-to-self
free
from domination or compulsion, a soldier’s relation-to-self is
precisely
influenced by those principles of domination and compulsion. A soldier
recognizes herself as an individual who submits to the will of the
chain of command.
This to me suggests that while Honneth has made a definite improvement
over
Fraser’s parity of participation by positing autonomy and
self-realization as
the normative core of his philosophy of recognition, he still succumbs
to
relativism, albeit to a lesser extent.
Similarly,
the characterization of
Honneth’s philosophy of recognition as being strong internal critique
is
questionable. Though it is possible to conceive of his notion of
historical
progress as being contained as a potentiality within the existing
order, the
turn to a past society as a means of evaluating the present is
troublesome. By
appealing to a past state of affairs as a method of determining the
moral
superiority of the present society, he is appealing to an external
principle, as
the norms of a past society are not necessarily implicit in the
present. Thus,
to use previous ‘recognition regimes’ as a yardstick by which we are to
measure
the present, we are in fact engaging in a form of external critique.
Although
Honneth has made explicit improvements upon Fraser’s shortcomings, as
well as
useful revisions of his own theory, he has not eradicated the problem
of
relativism. I agree with Bartol when he suggests that his notion of
historical
moral progress must be abandoned in order for Recognition Theory to
retain the
character of internal critique. At best, I believe Honneth to be
advocating a
mildly relativistic hybrid criticism, which holds aspects of both
internal and
external critique.
University of Windsor
Windsor, Ontario, Canada
About the Author
Works Cited
Bartol, Jordan. (2008) Is
Intercultural Critique
Possible? An Examination of Recognition Theory. Lyceum, 10(1).
Fraser, Nancy. and Axel Honneth
(2003) Redistribution or
Recognition? A Political Philosophical Exchange. Los Angeles:
Verso.
Honneth, Axel. (2002) “Grounding
Recognition: A Rejoinder
to Critical Questions.” Inquiry, 45, 499-519.
Kauppinen, Antti. (2002) “Reason,
Recognition, and
Internal Critique.” Inquiry, 45(4), 479-498.