Unhappy Humans and Happy Pigs
Joshua Seigal
John Stuart Mill is famous for having
expanded Bentham’s
utilitarianism to incorporate ‘higher’ and ‘lower’ pleasures. Nowhere
is this
better exemplified than in the dictum “better to be a human being
dissatisfied
than a pig satisfied.” In
this paper I argue that this dictum is inconsistent with
utilitarianism’s own
conception of the ‘good’. My argument shall proceed through several
stages: In
section one I present and defend a form of ‘hedonic calculus’, the use
of which
will be essential if we are to quantify happiness (as utilitarianism
aims to
do.) The calculus I suggest will be based on considerations as to how
we might
compare a human being’s happiness with that of a lower animal. I
present some
arguments as to why I think a utilitarian should accept this calculus.
In
section two I examine Mill’s conception of the ‘good’, and analyze his
famous
quotation in the light of this. I argue that, by this very criterion,
it is not
necessarily better to be a human being dissatisfied than a pig
satisfied. In
section three I examine how best to extricate ourselves from this
situation,
and I put forward the suggestion that if we want to maintain the belief
that it
is better to be a human being dissatisfied than a
pig satisfied (a
belief which, intuitively, we probably do wish to
maintain), it cannot
be based on utilitarian considerations.
Mill’s
quotation refers to
‘satisfaction’; henceforth I shall follow Bernard Williams in
using ‘happiness’ and ‘satisfaction’ interchangeably, so the question
of
whether or not it is better to be a human being dissatisfied than a pig
satisfied is equivalent to the question of whether or not it is better
to be an
unhappy human than it is to be a happy pig. I therefore argue that by
the criteria
of utilitarianism it is not better to be an unhappy human than it is to
be a
happy pig. It may be argued that pigs, unlike humans, are not really capable
of happiness. However, since the quotation sees fit to use
‘satisfaction’ as
applicable to both, and since I am using the terms ‘satisfied’ and
‘happy’
interchangeably, this need not be problematic.
Furthermore,
it may be claimed that
the reason it is better to be a human being dissatisfied than a pig
satisfied
is that the human has the capacity to contribute to a greater net level
of
happiness in society. In this essay I propose to
isolate an individual
human and an individual pig, and compare only the
respective happiness
of each, independently of the greater good to which they may or may not
have the
capacity to contribute.
I
Implicit in Mill’s quotation is the
assumption that human
and animal happiness is comparable. We therefore need to examine how
a
comparison could be carried out. I suggest that for a comparison, we
need a
means of quantification.
Mill
was concerned to show the
‘fundamental humanity’ of utilitarianism, and claimed, therefore, that
“a
beast’s pleasures do not satisfy a human being’s conception of
happiness”.
As
Smart notes,
the reluctance of a person to sacrifice his humanity for animal
happiness
indicates that human happiness somehow penetrates deeper,
is somehow
more profound, than that of a pig. Any calculus
that we use to quantify
happiness must therefore take into account the fact that human
happiness is,
prima facie, deeper.
I
assume that animals have sensory
experiences like we do, in the sense that, as with us, there is
‘something it
is like’ to be them.
The issue of what precisely differentiates us from
other animals is not
within the scope of this paper, but in terms of comparing our
respective
happiness it seems reasonable to suppose that the primary
differentiating
factor is our capacity for reflection, for having a
‘pro-attitude’
towards our own happiness.
Consider
a maximally happy human
(A) and a maximally happy animal (B): for B, we may suppose that the
satisfaction of desires constitutes the highest level of happiness. The
capacity for reflection in A, however, necessitates
that we add another
level when examining A’s capacity for happiness. So, a maximally happy
person
will not only have all his desires satisfied, he will also be able to
somehow reflect
on his situation, and know that all his desires are
satisfied. Animals,
it seems, lack this capacity for self-reflection.
How,
then, are we to incorporate
this consideration into a calculus? Taking the person’s capacity for
self-reflection into account, we may suppose a two-tier view, whereby a
person’s pro-attitude is included in the calculation of his overall
happiness:
a person is fully happy if he is happy, and he knows/recognizes
this to be the case (and is happy about it). Given that an animal is
unable to
reflect upon its own happiness, a fully happy animal is not able to
fulfill
this second condition; it is not able to know/recognize that it is
happy. A fully
happy person is therefore happy on two levels, a
fully happy animal
merely on one. Thus, if we were to award points for
happiness at each of
the levels, a fully happy person would be worth two
points, a fully
happy animal one.
It
follows of course that a fully
happy person is happier than a fully happy animal: level-one happiness
for each
consists in the mere satisfaction of desires, but a person’s overall
capacity for happiness is greater, by dint of the person’s being able
to reflect
on his level-one happiness. Thus, if happiness is the
criterion of the
good, it is better to be a satisfied person than a satisfied pig
(recall that I
am using ‘happiness’ and ‘satisfaction’ interchangeably).
This,
however, is not Mill’s
claim. He claims that it is better to be a dissatisfied
(unhappy) person
than it is to be a satisfied pig. How, then, do a dissatisfied person
and a
satisfied pig compare according to our calculus? It may be recalled
that a
fully satisfied animal is worth one point (being incapable of
self-reflection).
How much is a dissatisfied person worth? It is obvious that a
dissatisfied
person is less happy than a fully happy person, and, given that a fully
happy
person scores two points (one for happiness on each of the two levels)
a
dissatisfied (unhappy) person must score less than
two points.
Perhaps
a dissatisfied person could
score less than two but higher than one (and thus
still be less happy
than a fully happy person and more happy than a fully happy pig). It
has been
suggested that a person’s happiness can be viewed on two levels, and on
each
level a person can either be happy or unhappy. Thus, a fully happy
person is
happy on both of the two levels. A less than happy person is therefore
only
happy on one of the two levels, and scores at most one point, whilst a
fully unhappy
person is happy on neither level, and scores zero.
Some
interesting things follow: a
totally depressed (i.e. maximally unhappy) person is less happy than a
happy
pig, so it would, according to the calculus, be better to be a happy
pig than a
depressed person.
However, we need not equate the dissatisfied person
with the maximally
unhappy person. Since the unhappy person is lacking happiness
on either of
the two levels (but need not do so on both), he is worth one point. We
have
seen that a happy pig is also worth one point, so a happy pig is equal
in
happiness to an unhappy person.
However,
why should utilitarians
accept this calculus? One of the reasons, I believe, is that
utilitarianism
requires that happiness be quantifiable. The ‘points’ system I have
suggested
seems at best ad hoc, but if happiness is to be
quantifiable there needs
to be some kind of unit of quantification. As
Williams says,
happiness must be ‘calculable’. Another reason why the calculus I have
outlined
should be accepted by a utilitarian is that it is based on reasonable
considerations as to the differences between humans and animals, a
comparison
that is rendered necessary by Mill’s quotation. If it is
the capacity
for reflection that differentiates humans from animals, then human
happiness
would seem to require the extra level that I have suggested. Thus,
given that
happiness must be quantifiable, we can assign values to the respective
happiness of humans and animals that take into account this basic
difference
between them.
II
Implicit in the claim that one thing
is better than another
is a conception as to what it is that makes something ‘good’. As
Geoffrey
Scarre has highlighted, for utilitarianism to be tenable, there needs
to be an
“organising feature of experience which functions as the common
denominator of
good.” For
utilitarianism, then, ‘happiness’ serves this purpose. Happiness, Mill
claims,
is the only thing that is intrinsically good, all other things being
good
inasmuch as they are a means to, or part of, this end.
Now,
the calculus in the above
section shows that it is not the case that an
unhappy person contains
more happiness than a happy pig. Of course, we haven’t yet confronted
Mill’s
claim that the type of happiness is important, but,
when we consider
happiness purely quantitatively, as I believe utilitarianism must, we
can see
that, taking into account differences between human and animal natures,
an
unhappy person does not score more ‘points’ than a happy pig. I have,
furthermore,
attempted to argue that such a ‘points’ system is really the only
viable way of
making utilitarianism work: Mill’s quotation requires that happiness be
comparable, comparison requires that happiness be calculable, and
calculability
necessitates units of quantification.
We
are now in a position to observe
how the claim that it is ‘better’ to be a human being dissatisfied than
a pig
satisfied functions, and how it is incompatible with utilitarianism’s
conception of the good. In section one we saw that an unhappy person is
not
happier than a happy pig. We can also now observe the fact that the
phrase
‘better than’ asserts of one thing that it contains more ‘good’ than
something
else. So, if utilitarianism’s conception of the good is ‘happiness’,
then to say
of one thing A that it is better than another thing B is to say that A
contains
more happiness than B. So, when Mill claims that “it is better to be a
human
being dissatisfied than a pig satisfied”, his own criterion of the good
renders
this equivalent to saying “an unhappy human contains more happiness
than a
happy pig.” But this is exactly what the calculus in section one has
shown to
be false.
Thus,
if the criterion of the
‘good’ is happiness, it is not better to be a human being dissatisfied
than a
pig satisfied.
III
From what has been said thus far, we
can observe a certain
inconsistency in the following two propositions:
1)
Utilitarianism is correct
2) It is better to be a human being dissatisfied than a pig satisfied.
Where, then, do we go from here? I
have interpreted
‘utilitarianism is correct’ as containing ‘happiness is the criterion
of the
good’ as a necessary condition. Perhaps a way out is to challenge this
and
argue that utilitarianism does not have to proceed
using ‘happiness’ as
the criterion of the good.
As
Smart has highlighted,
‘Ideal’ utilitarianism holds that other things, besides happiness, have
intrinsic value. Smart calls Mill a ‘quasi-Ideal utilitarian’. If this
is the
case then it may be that we can accommodate the view that it is better
to be a
human being dissatisfied than a pig satisfied on grounds other
than
happiness into a utilitarian framework. This, however, seems an obtuse
interpretation of Mill, who explicitly states that whilst “the
ingredients of
happiness are very various” it
is happiness itself that is the only thing
possessing intrinsic value.
It
could further be argued that
Mill’s conception of ‘higher’ and ‘lower’ pleasures means that human
happiness
is intrinsically better than that of a pig, since it is of an
altogether
different, higher type. If this is the case, then
we may be able to
maintain ‘happiness is the criterion of the good’ as a necessary
condition of
utilitarianism, whilst adding the qualification that this should be
construed
as higher happiness.
As
H.B Acton notes Mill
was perhaps influenced by Whewell’s observation that if only quantity
(and
not quality) is taken into account, the Greatest Happiness Principle
becomes
the ‘Greatest Animal Happiness Principle’. However, given that
utilitarianism
is based on a conception of the good as comparable, calculable and
additive, it
seems as though happiness, as the criterion of the good, can differ
only in degree,
and not in kind, for how can two kinds
of things be comparable?
John Grote, in a very early commentary on utilitarianism, claimed that
“a
consistent utilitarian can scarcely hold the difference of quality
in
pleasures in any sense”.
Things admit of comparison only in the degree to which they fulfill a
certain
end, so for human beings’ and pigs’ happiness to be comparable they
must not
differ in kind, otherwise the very notion of comparison wouldn’t make
sense. In
bringing in ‘higher’ happiness as a different kind
of happiness
altogether, Mill is destroying the very commensurability that is
required to
affect a comparison. ‘Higher’ pleasures thus seem to possess a
non-utilitarian
value, and therefore seem inappropriate in a utilitarian system.
Given
that utilitarianism does indeed
seem to claim happiness as the sole criterion of the good, and given
that the
quantification and comparison of happiness is more easily made sense of
when we
consider degree rather than kind,
it does indeed seem as though
we need to do away with either 1 or 2.
Which
one should it be? In
presenting the calculus in section one I attempted to adumbrate how a
utilitarian should deal with the problem of whether or not it is better
to be a
happy pig or an unhappy human. We could therefore see that the way
utilitarianism must treat the problem cannot yield a verification of
Mill’s dictum.
However, the calculus seemed somehow inappropriate. Since I presented
some
reasons as to why I think such a calculus is indispensable for a
utilitarian
(inasmuch as he wishes to compare human and animal happiness), any
lingering
feelings of inappropriateness may be due to the inherent implausibility
of
utilitarianism. As Williams says, “utilitarianism cannot hope to make
sense, at
any serious level…of human desire and action at all, and hence only
very poor
sense of what was supposed to be its own specialty, happiness.” Given
this consideration, I suggest that the most likely candidate for
abandonment is
1.
At
any rate, if we hold that 1 and
2 are inconsistent (as I have claimed that we should), and
we believe
that it is somehow better to be a human being dissatisfied than a pig
satisfied, we should hold this belief independently
of utilitarian
considerations. Unfortunately however, it is not within the scope of
this paper
to inquire further into what our considerations should in fact be.
University College London
London, UK
About the Author
Works Cited
Allen, Colin. ‘Animal
Consciousness’, Stanford
Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
Leahy, Michael P T. ‘Against
Animal Liberation: Putting
Animals in Perspective’, Routledge, 1994.
Locke, John. ‘An Essay Concerning
Human Understanding’,
Everyman, 1947
Mill, John Stuart.
‘Utilitarianism’, JM Dent and sons,
1972.
Moore, Andrew. ‘Hedonism’,
Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy, 2004.
Nagel, Thomas ‘What is it Like to
be a Bat?’ in
Metaphysics: a Guide and Anthology (eds. Crane and Farkas), Oxford,
2004.
Scarre, Geoffrey.
‘Utilitarianism’, Routledge, 1996.
Shaw, William H. ‘Contemporary
Ethics: Taking Account of
Utilitarianism’, Blackwell, 1999.
Smart, JJC, and Bernard Williams,
‘Utilitarianism: For
and Against’, Cambridge University Press, 1973.
Williams, Bernard. ‘Morality’,
Cambridge University Press, 1972.